Transcendentalism and Abolitionism: The Institution vs. the Individual
As Ralph Waldo Emerson’s
Self-Reliance makes abundantly clear,
Transcendentalists deeply distrusted institutions, hated the way they
suppressed the individual’s agency and natural inclinations. They were,
therefore, unafraid to buck the system, even when the federal government tried
to force them to comply with the Fugitive Slave Law. Emerson declared “I will
not obey it, by God;” the Unitarian minister and reformer Theodore Parker
was very nearly indicted for obstructing justice after attempting to rescue the
fugitive slave Anthony Burns; both Bronson Alcott
and Henry David Thoreau spent time in jail for refusing to pay taxes to an
unjust government and volunteered their homes for use in the Underground
Railroad (qtd. in Gougeon xxxix; Commager 242; Schreiner 110, 161; Thoreau 974).
However, their apathy toward institutions meant that they viewed evils like
slavery as issues that had to be resolved not through institutional (such as
the government and even abolitionist organizations) means but through
individual moral reform (Elkins 168). Individuals had to change first, and
society would follow, not the other way around (Gougeon xi). Transcendentalists
had the duty to reveal the evils and spread the truth, but the individual had
to change himself (Fredrickson 11). Before the 1840s, therefore, while
Transcendentalists theoretically opposed slavery, many were reluctant to be publicly associated with abolition organizations like the American
Anti-Slavery Society.
Aside from their
dislike of institutions, Transcendentalists had another reason for not publicly and loudly taking up the abolition cause: Slavery was too narrow a
cause. “Single-issue moral reform efforts like abolition missed the point that
moral reform must always seek the renewal of the entire individual. Morality is
not, after all, piecemeal” (Gougeon xi). Man was inherently good, but he had
lost his way, been separated from Nature and her divine truth. To cure that, he
had to be changed entirely; slavery was merely a single symptom of a much
larger and more pervasive disease. From a Transcendentalist point of view, it
made little sense to attempt a cure anywhere but the root of the problem, the
soul. “They have fallen into the common error of enthusiasts,” wrote William Ellery Channing of abolitionists in Slavery, “that of exaggerating their object, of feeling as if no
evil existed but that which they opposed, and as if no guilt could be compared
with that of countenancing or upholding it” (153). Many Transcendentalists were
abolitionists, and their stances would grow more and more extreme as the
passing years revealed society’s stubbornness regarding slavery, but in the
early years, the 1820s and 1830s, many Transcendentalists agreed with the
sentiment Emerson voiced in Self-Reliance:
“If an angry bigot assumes this bountiful cause of Abolition […], why should I
not say to him, ‘Go love thy infant; love thy woodchopper: be good-natured and
modest: have that grace; and never varnish your hard, uncharitable ambition
with this incredible tenderness for black folk a thousand miles off. Thy love
afar is spite at home’” (Elkins 167; Emerson 271-72).
Emerson’s comment on
the “hard, uncharitable ambition” of abolitionists reveals yet another reason
many Transcendentalists held abolitionists at arm’s length for many years
(Emerson 272). In their attempts to end slavery, extreme abolitionists like
William Lloyd Garrison, naturally the people who became the figureheads of the
movement, used belligerent and aggressive methods to sway people to their side.
“The tone of their newspapers, as far as I have seen them,” wrote Channing,
“has often been fierce, bitter, and abusive” (153). Because Transcendentalists
believed in man as the ultimate authority over himself, these bullying,
pressuring, condemning methods drew their disapproval (Elkins 167; Gara 37). Telling
the truth was one thing; forcing it down people’s throats, however, was encroaching
on man’s inviolate individual judgment and morals.
Ironically, however,
Transcendentalism also placed a significant amount of pressure on the
individual who knew the truth; knowing the truth but not acting on it was
significantly worse than following in blind ignorance. In that vein, Thoreau’s Resistance to Civil Government
frequently expresses the individual’s responsibility to at least not support
evil but preferably to resist it outright (968-69). These opposing tenets –
allowing no one to force you into anything without failing to act entirely –
created an interesting and difficult dichotomy. Elizabeth Palmer Peabody, for example, the Transcendentalist educational
reformer and eventual abolitionist, deeply strained her relationship with her
sister and her brother-in-law Nathaniel Hawthorne over the Hawthornes’ apparent
apathy and inaction toward slavery (Ronda 264-65).
No comments:
Post a Comment